Vidyanand
Nanjundiah
ab and
Santosh
Sathe
b
aDepartment of Molecular Reproduction, Development and Genetics, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore 560012, India
bCentre for Ecological Sciences, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore 560012, India. E-mail: vidya@ces.iisc.ernet.in
First published on 24th January 2011
In social selection the phenotype of an individual depends on its own genotype as well as on the phenotypes, and so genotypes, of other individuals. This makes it impossible to associate an invariant phenotype with a genotype: the social context is crucial. Descriptions of metazoan development, which often is viewed as the acme of cooperative social behaviour, ignore or downplay this fact. The implicit justification for doing so is based on a group-selectionist point of view. Namely, embryos are clones, therefore all cells have the same evolutionary interest, and the visible differences between cells result from a common strategy. The reasoning is flawed, because phenotypic heterogeneity within groups can result from contingent choices made by cells from a flexible repertoire as in multicellular development. What makes that possible is phenotypic plasticity, namely the ability of a genotype to exhibit different phenotypes. However, co-operative social behaviour with division of labour requires that different phenotypes interact appropriately, not that they belong to the same genotype, or have overlapping genetic interests. We sketch a possible route to the evolution of social groups that involves many steps: (a) individuals that happen to be in spatial proximity benefit simply by virtue of their number; (b) traits that are already present act as preadaptations and improve the efficiency of the group; and (c) new adaptations evolve under selection in the social context—that is, via interactions between individuals—and further strengthen group behaviour. The Dictyostelid or cellular slime mould amoebae (CSMs) become multicellular in an unusual way, by the aggregation of free-living cells. In nature the resulting group can be genetically homogeneous (clonal) or heterogeneous (polyclonal); in either case its development, which displays strong cooperation between cells (to the extent of so-called altruism) is not affected. This makes the CSMs exemplars for the study of social behaviour.
Insight, innovation, integrationAn analysis of cooperative behaviour in the cellular slime mould amoebae (CSMs) offers insights into the evolution of social groups (at one end) and multicellular development (at the other). In the CSMs one can verify experimentally that the phenotype of an amoeba depends both on its own genotype and on the phenotypes of other amoebae: every individual in a group forms part of every other individual's environment. Thus the notion of individual phenotype is meaningful only within a clearly defined social context. Rather than shared genes, appropriately interacting phenotypes are the essential requirement for group life. These insights may be useful for understanding abnormal development as well. |
This leads to the concept of social selection, in which individual phenotype, and so individual fitness, is meaningful only in a given social context. Therefore the phenotype is ‘non-autonomous’: it depends on traits exhibited by other individuals, whether those traits are similar or dissimilar to the one being monitored in the focal individual.1,2 For non-autonomy to be meaningful, the individual phenotype must be flexible or plastic, i.e., capable of being influenced by the environment. An extreme case of plasticity is when different individuals of the same genotype give rise to different phenotypes in the same environment. Individual and group behaviour in the cellular slime moulds (CSMs) illustrate these concepts nicely, and also provide useful insights into the evolutionary basis of social behaviour in groups, including multicellular embryos—generally.
We first lay the groundwork by explaining our use of ‘social selection’ and ‘superorganism’; ‘non-autonomy’, ‘niche construction’ and ‘phenotypic plasticity’, terms that are relevant in the context of social selection, are introduced next. They are linked as follows: natural selection can act on phenotypes that depend on interactions with other phenotypes and so cannot be considered in isolation (social selection); social selection can take place in tightly organised groups of the same species (superorganism); the ultimate superorganism is the multicellular embryo; differentiation during multicellular development depends on reciprocal phenotype-moulding interactions between different cell types (non autonomy, niche construction); and behind it all is the capacity of single genotypes to exhibit different phenotypes (phenotypic plasticity). This will turn out to be somewhat discursive but should help the reader to appreciate that significant concepts have not always been used consistently, but for a good reason: it can help not to push definitions too hard and to retain a certain degree of elasticity in usage.
The second part sketches a plausible route for the evolution of group-level traits that begins with a purely physical advantage of increased size. Preadaptations reinforce those advantages by bringing into play similar traits in all members of the group. Next, group effects are reinforced via social selection for newly evolved reciprocal interactions between group members leading to division of labour. The examples that we list in support under these heads are mostly drawn from the social insects (the Volvocales are another well-studied case, not discussed here).3,4 The third and longest part of the paper draws attention to the fact that observations made on the development (or, equivalently, social behaviour) of the Dictyostelid amoebae or cellular slime moulds (CSMs) support the evolutionary route just sketched. Traces of the steps listed above can be seen in present-day CSM species, and there is considerable evidence for the importance of reciprocal interactions between cells. We end the paper by raising the question whether the concept of social selection can be useful for the study of not only normal, but also pathological multicellular development.
Crook8 distinguished between four kinds of social selection based on (a) inter-individual competition for resources essential for reproduction, (b) competition for mates, (c) competition for resources required in the course of parental care, and finally, (d) cooperation towards establishing a social unit that would benefit the offspring of the co-operators and possibly their kin. According to him ‘social selection’ could accommodate conventional individual-level selection with no direct interactions (except possibly with offspring), sexual selection in the sense of Darwin and selection based on shared interests, whether or not the interests were identical. West-Eberhard9 discussed all this and more in a classic analysis. She drew attention to three features of social selection that are relevant for us: non-heritable variation, that can be significant for the maintenance of group life; facultative (as opposed to genetic) ‘switches’, that can lead to alternative behaviours in a social group, and, mutually exclusive tasks performed by the members of a group, which can follow from the above. Wolf et al.10 extended the quantitative treatment of interacting phenotypes begun by Moore et al.1 and used ‘social selection’ to mean ‘a process distinct from other forms of natural selection’ which is likely to occur ‘whenever individual fitness varies as a result of interactions with conspecifics’. For Nesse11 social selection was a ‘subtype of natural selection in which choices made by other individuals influence [an individual's] fitness and change gene frequencies’: selection was followed by evolution, implying that the phenotypes (i.e., different behaviours) in question were associated with different genotypes.
A slight rewording of Nesse's formulation provides what in our opinion is a broad and practical definition of social selection: it is a form of natural selection in which phenotypes of other individuals influence an individual's fitness. Ipso facto, social selection operates in groups, because the character of a group is defined by the extent to which its members interact. The interactions can be direct, mediated via another member of the group, or via the physical or (other) biotic environment. In the absence of any influence of one individual on another, ‘group’ would be just another name for a collection of individuals who, for all practical purposes, lead a solitary existence.
So social selection acts within groups, involves phenotypic interactions and has consequences for fitness. ‘Fitness’ can apply to the individual vis-à-vis the rest of the group or to the group in relation to other groups. Other qualifications can be made as applicable in specific situations. Our emphasis is on phenotypic interactions between individuals within groups, whether or not they are accompanied by a ‘convergence of interests among group members’.9Table 1 outlines the circumstances in which social selection can operate and the nature of the relevant group. Except for brief allusions, the rest of this paper does not deal with sexual selection or interactions between members of different species, though both are important topics, the latter particularly so for behaviour and multicellular development.12
Is inter-individual social selection mediated via | Group consists of | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Predator and prey | Potential mates | Parasite and host | Two species (symbiosis/mutualism) | Cellular slime moulds | Social insect colony | Metazoan embryo | |
interacting phenotypes? | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes |
shared reproductive interests? | No | Yes | No | Yes | Possible, not necessary | Possible, not necessary | Yes |
different phenotypes? | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Possible | Possible | Possible |
different genotypes? | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Possible | Possible | No |
Despite these precedents, Wheeler is frequently credited with being the first person explicitly to draw an analogy between a social insect (ant) colony and a multicellular organism.15 He too compared the various sterile castes to somatic cells and the reproductive caste(s) to germ cells and subsequently coined the word ‘super-organism’ for social insects generally, because their colonies were akin to ‘a living whole bent on preserving its moving equilibrium and its integrity’.16 Fisher echoed Weismann in emphasising the unitary structure of a social insect colony but pointed out that whenever the queen was heterozygous at a locus, genetic variation between workers could be expected, and that could result in within-colony polymorphism and selection.17 Emerson18 expanded on the notion of a ‘biological individual’ as ‘an organized biological unit relatively independent of other units’ and proposed that entities ranging from genes to cells to multicellular organisms to societies (including those of social insects) and interspecific groups should be thought of as individuals, each at its appropriate level of organisation.
In the sources quoted above there is no attempt to restrict ‘superorganism’ to the highly eusocial insects. It is only recently that Hölldobler and Wilson have attempted to categorise superorganisms into different grades: ‘The social organizations, however, vary greatly among the social insect species, and we can recognize different evolutionary grades of superorganismic organization …A “primitive” (less derived) grade is represented by several ponerine species, where members of the colony have full reproductive potential and there is considerable interindividual reproductive competition within each colony. Highly advanced grades are represented…by the leafcutter ant genera Atta and Acromyrmex and the Oecophylla weaver ants, where the queen caste is the sole reproductive, and the hundreds of thousands of sterile workers occur as morphological subcastes..’. They continue (questionably) with ‘These societies exhibit the ultimate superorganism states, where interindividual conflict within the colony is minimal or nonexistent’.19 Colony-level selection as the defining element of what constitutes a superorganism is a relatively recent development and has saddled the concept with unnecessary controversy. For us, superorganism will simply mean a group of individual organisms or cells that resembles a multicellular organism—that is, functions like an integral social or biological unit (taken from http://www.bugsinthenews.com/Definition%20of%20Superorganism.htm), with the added proviso that reproductive division of labour may or may not exist.
There is abundant evidence for phenotype-phenotype interactions and feedbacks in multicellular development. The clearest instances come from what developmental biologists call regulative development.20 In a regulative embryo the removal of a part of the embryo—sometimes as much as one-half—results in the reorganisation of the remaining portion, which goes on to form a normally-proportioned whole. The most dramatic demonstration of this was by Driesch, who showed that a single amphibian blastomere at the two-cell stage, that normally gave rise to a left or right half-embryo, would develop into an entire embryo if the other blastomere was removed.20 The capacity of tissues to regenerate, and of body parts to maintain their relative proportions (analogous to regulation), are further evidences for the existence of intercellular communication, competition and feedback.23–25 Thus the requirements for social selection to act are present in embryos.
Not surprisingly, multicellular organisation has been compared to a society. Schleiden said so much before Darwin (whose comparison was in the opposite direction), apparently without referring to social insects. In 1858 Virchow made Schleiden's analogy explicit: ‘[Schleiden]… declared that each cell has an individual existence, and that the life of an organism comes from the way in which the cells work together’ and ‘Rudolph Virchow took Schleiden's observation a step further. He declared that “the composition of the major organism, the so-called individual, must be likened to a kind of social arrangement or society, in which a number of separate existences are dependent upon one another, in such a way, however, that each element possesses its own peculiar activity and carries out its own task by its own powers” (both quotations from Bloom26).
At the same time, the deep similarities between multicellular organisms and social groups cannot be ignored. As mentioned, Emerson was one of the many who drew an analogy between division of labour in social insects and somatic cell differentiation in multicellular development, with reproductives being compared to the germ line.18 He extended the analogy by bringing in other features: regeneration, the restoration of missing components (regulation), interactions between units and dominance, all of which are seen in social insect groups and embryos. These points have been advanced repeatedly by Bonner, with metabolic coordination, integration by means of mutual communication and specialised reproduction as the common underlying themes.27,37,38
These commonalities risk being obscured by the assertion that the embryo is a constitutive structure (a group of genetically identical cells) whereas a social organism is a facultative entity (a group of genetically more or less diverse individuals). The assertion is valid but irrelevant. Ever since Price's21 demonstration that trait frequency change in evolution can be partitioned into changes based on within-group selection and between-group covariance, we have known that individual selection and group selection, involving kin or otherwise, can be treated under a common rubric. To be sure, Price's formulation has no bearing on the utility of one or the other description. In studying a trait and the factors that impinge on it, there may be more to be gained by focussing on the individual than the group, or the other way round; it depends on the situation. Also, in certain circumstances, both views may need to be adopted simultaneously (consider the example of a stray lioness attempting to join an existing pride). The virtue of Price's formulation is that it separates the two central players in the evolutionary origin and maintenance of the group, namely (direct or indirect) competition within groups and between groups. In any case, as said above certain traits in social groups stand out as having a ‘group’ character, however much one wishes to adopt an individual-level viewpoint. Group longevity, which affects the success of the group and its constituents, could be an example. Longevity depends in part on metabolic efficiency, which is a collective property of the networks of food and energy transfer in the group.28
Canalisation and the norm of reaction point to contrasting aspects of genetic flexibility. Canalisation shows that different genotypes can lead to the same phenotype in similar environments, whereas the norm of reaction shows phenotypic plasticity: the same genotype can lead to different phenotypes in different environments. Multicellular development displays both features. The first aspect of genetic flexibility is exhibited, as already discussed, by the masking of genetic differences between different ‘wild-type’ individuals. Cell-type differentiation provides a striking example of the second aspect. Here the different environments may be dependent on positions within the embryo (e.g., inside-outside differences in the mammalian blastula), parental influences (e.g., via the egg cytoplasm, a maternal product, or within the maternal body) or phenotypes of other cells; different temporal environments, meaning different developmental histories, may also play a role. Phenotypes can differ even in the absence of a proximate cause. The genotypes and environments may be the same, but the developmental histories of the individuals in question may have been different (as Novick and Weiner showed of Escherichia coli and the lac operon).31 Finally, stochastic effects—‘noise’—can determine which of two alternative states of gene expression is actually chosen, and therefore which phenotype is expressed.32,33
Phenotypic plasticity can be manifested in yet another way and that is in the phenomenon known as niche construction. ‘Niche construction’ originally referred to the ability of organisms to modify their environment—to have a hand in constructing their own niche and so to influence how selection acts on them (beaver dams and earthworm burrows are examples often cited).34 It is a pervasive feature of the life cycle of many organisms and has been discussed as a likely major force in evolution.35 Gilbert and Epel point out that niche construction is a useful concept in a rather different situation, that of interacting phenotypes in multicellular development.12 As they argue, niche construction is another name for the phenomenon of embryonic induction (they go on to point out that it also applies to inter-organism interactions of developmental importance).
Embryonic induction is said to take place when signalling between two sets of cells that are in contact, and have each attained the appropriate competences, leads to differentiation. If the interaction fails to take place when it should, the course of differentiation is altered. An example from Gilbert and Epel is the ‘complex dialogue’ of reciprocal interactions that takes place in mammalian development between the neural tissue of the presumptive retina and the ectoderm of the presumptive lens, leading each to differentiate into its final state. Developmental geneticists inferred the existence of intercellular interactions from the observation that many mutations showed cell non-autonomous effects: the aberrant phenotype was manifested in a cell which was itself genetically wild-type.36 In the sense used by us, niche construction in embryonic development leads to non-autonomous differentiation; the fact that it does so implies that the cellular genotype can exhibit a range of phenotypes. The language and the conclusion apply equally well to individual phenotypes in social groups.
The phenomenon of more than one potential or actual unit of reproduction functioning as part of a larger whole (that is composed of similar or dissimilar units) is common in biology. The unit can be a gene or DNA sequence, a chromosome, an intracellular organelle, a cell, a tissue (organ) or an entire organism—a microbe, plant or animal. In many cases the whole displays ‘emergent’ properties, that is, modes of functioning that are not seen, or sometimes not possible, in its constituent units. When that happens, one should attempt to account for the property in question (“X”) in terms of the properties that the units display when examined separately; and only when that seems not to work, to look for other explanations.
Thus one should begin by seeing whether X can be explained as a straightforward consequence of the fact that the group consists of more than one unit. Perhaps X resembles what chemists call a colligative property, namely one that depends merely on number—for example, the elevation in the boiling point of a solution as the concentration of the solute is increased (except that in biology, the nature of the ‘solute’ cannot be ignored). Simply by being part of a crowd, so to speak, an individual may gain advantages. For example, the probability of capture by a predator could decrease. Or, because a predator must consider the risk of hurting itself in a physical collision (as with bird or fish flocks), numbers could act as a deterrent. In both situations the extent of protection should go up with group size. In the process, the group may develop a spatial structure that derives from nothing more than each member acting independently in trying to do the same thing (e.g., staying as far from the periphery as possible).39
The well-known ‘square root of n’ rule—more precisely, the Central Limit Theorem of statistics40—may be behind apparent group-level adaptations that are an automatic consequence of group size. For example, given some distribution in the efficiency with which an individual performs a task, the performance of the same task by a group of similar individuals is expected to become ever more reliable as their number increases. Therefore, if (for example) an estimate of the amount of forage to be gathered in the future is important for running a beehive efficiently, it helps to increase the number of foragers. It has been proposed that this principle may have been one of the factors behind the evolution of sociality in bees.42,43
In an environment that varies over space and/or time, the appropriate measure of long-term fitness (of the individual or the group as the case may be) is the geometric mean, which depends on both the arithmetic mean and the variance—in fact it decreases with increasing variance;44 the essence of the argument goes back all the way to Daniel Bernoulli.41 Thus, given that variance decreases with size as discussed above, the commonly observed tendency of size increase in evolution4 may be a consequence of selection for the increased reliability that is provided by a larger size. A different advantage provided by number may be traced to the fact the ratio of volume to surface, and therefore a measure of how successfully a system can be maintained in a stable condition in the face of the tendency to equilibrate with the environment, increases as a function of the size (meaning typical linear extent) of the system. This too could have been a factor behind the evolution of multicellularity.
When a ‘colligative’ explanation does not suffice, one looks for an explanation at a different level. Now, over and above the properties of the individual units, one takes into account the interactions that occur between them. Here it is useful to make a distinction between two situations. Interactions could be based on traits that already existed in the solitary state; or, a trait in question may have been absent in single cells but evolved subsequent to the evolution of group living. The first situation involves a preadaptation which may or may not have served an adaptive role previously; if it did not, one would call it an exaptation.11 A preadaptation that is relevant to group living is when an individual's traits vary in a stage-specific manner over the life cycle. For example, in both primitive45 and advanced46 social insects there is the phenomenon of age-polyethism, defined as a ‘statistical shift in the activities of workers over time’47; rather than absolute age, what counts is the relative age within a cohort. And when, as is likely, a randomly assembled group happens to contain individuals of different ages, the outcome can be adaptive division of labour.48 Another possibility can be envisaged when the development of the traits of interest depends on a small number of inputs, in the extreme case just one. Then the individuals in whom the inputs happened to differ (even by chance), would exhibit different traits.49
Thus group living would have been reinforced whenever the stability or the efficiency of the group was enhanced by the expression of traits that were already present. However, if the units that made up a group had been living by themselves earlier, and if the initial selective advantage of group life was slight, solitary living and group living would have co-existed. The outcome can be compared to the equilibrium that is reached in a reversible chemical reaction of the sort A ↔ B, except that in our case A stands for solitary existence and B for group existence. The equilibrium situation reflects the relative a priori probabilities of the two states (and not, as in a chemical reaction, the probabilities of transitions between them). The coexistence of A and B would be favoured by spatial or temporal fluctuations in environmental conditions, or by trade-offs between the advantages of group life (e.g., improved chances of survival) and its disadvantages (e.g., lowered rate of reproduction). Alternatively, A and B could represent evolutionarily stable phenotypic compositions (ESCs) of genotypes.50
A decisive step in the evolution of social behaviour must have been taken when ‘truly social’ properties emerged, based on traits that did not pre-exist but originated de novo. It is evident that the traits in question must have involved interactions between individuals. They would depend on signals from one individual that influenced the behaviour of a second individual in a way that fed back on the signaller. If the interests of the two individuals overlap little, signalling is selected or not depending on its consequences for the signaller and recipient, assessed independently. However, if the interests overlap significantly (say because the traits complement each other), the situation would automatically lend itself to selection at the level of the group; signalling between potential mates is an example. As far as any member of the group is concerned, all other members form part of its environment and specify the constraints to which it has to adapt; each member of the group is simultaneously actor and responder. If an adaptive outcome does evolve, it will be identified as a specifically group-level trait that improves the reliable maintenance of social behaviour while benefiting the long-term reproductive interest of the individual. A well-studied example of reciprocal feedbacks in group behaviour is the allocation of workers to different behavioural castes in a eusocial insect colony in which the relative proportions of different castes are restored by the group after they have been altered experimentally.51 As far as we are aware, the necessary manipulations have not been carried out on primitively eusocial insects. Still, the observations provide striking evidence of interactions between phenotypes and feedbacks in social groups.
Assuming that what we have called truly social properties exist, how should we go about looking for them, keeping in mind the fact that what we see may be the result of many generations of evolutionary modification? A good strategy would be to compare homogeneous and heterogeneous groups where the components that make up the heterogeneous group exhibit clear differences in traits when they form groups by themselves. For the strategy to work, the differences should reflect stable properties of the members of either group. Ideally, this means something correlated with the genotype. Then, each homogeneous group will be genetically uniform and the heterogeneous group will be genetically mosaic. Under these circumstances, if the phenotype of a member of the heterogeneous group is influenced by the presence of other individuals, the influence can easily be detected. In the case of the cellular slime mould (CSM) or Dictyostelid amoebae, manipulations of this sort are straightforward and a huge amount of experimental data is available. In the next section, after a brief introduction to the CSM life cycle, we draw attention to diverse findings that can be interpreted within the framework of social selection.
Post-aggregation development involves a constant number of cells (in the laboratory, after one has taken into account stragglers in the cell division cycle that may divide soon after the food supply is removed). Aggregation is followed by complex morphogenetic movements both within the mass and by the mass as a whole, giving rise finally to a terminally differentiated ‘adult’ structure known as the fruiting body. Within the fruiting body, some cells make up a ball of stress-resistant spores and other cells form a stalk of dead cells that supports the spore mass at its end. This arrangement, with spores raised above the substrate, is believed to aid passive dispersal. If dispersal occurs to an environment where food is available, each spore can germinate and the amoeba that emerges can feed, grow, divide and set off a new multicellular stage after the food runs out.
Spores can be compared to germ cells and the stalk can be thought of as the equivalent of somatic tissue. However, in contrast to the cells of a metazoan embryo, the CSM amoebae that form a social group need not be genetically identical. Under natural conditions they can constitute a clone,59 belong to different genotypes within the same species,60–64 or, rarely, belong to different species, ref. 65 and unpublished work. When an aggregate is genetically heterogeneous, phenotypic heterogeneity can be a reflection of diverging reproductive interests between the amoebae in a group. Even if the aggregate consists of a clone of cells, individual reproductive interests need not coincide: phenotypic differences between cells can be expected to be translated into reproductive differences (as indeed they are). Here, though the situation appears to lend itself to a kin-selection based explanation, one must keep in mind that what may be at work is individual-level selection and physiological dominance.66 The presence of different genotypes in a group makes the likelihood of phenotypic differences more likely, and also easier to verify.
CSM development occurs within a specified range of the physical environment, and its outcome can differ significantly within that range. In Dictyostelium discoideum, a decrease in humidity speeds up development,67 whereas a decrease in temperature slows it down67 and increases the distance over which amoebae can be attracted.68 Starved cultures develop faster, and aggregates are smaller, in light than in the dark.67 These effects of light are marked in the case of Polysphondylium pallidum, in which aggregation cannot commence in the dark.69 The nature of the substrate on which development occurs also has a significant effect on development (for example, whether it is relatively smooth or granular), ref. 70 and unpublished work.
Interestingly, there can be significant differences between supposedly wild-type strains in the biochemical details of development. A prominent instance involves variations in the kinetics of production and release of two proteins that modulate the strength of the cAMP signal between its release by one D. discoideumcell and reception by another, namely a secreted cAMP phosphodiesterase and its inhibitor.71,72 The implication is that the norm of reaction for the species as a whole—with its members being of different ‘wild-type’ genotypes—extends over a broader range than the norm for a single individual. Not unexpectedly, mutants show a stronger sensitivity to environmental conditions than the wild-type does, which points to a component of Genotype × Environment interaction in overall phenotypic variation. For example, some mutants of D. discoideum are unable to aggregate on growth medium—that is, when they are plated with bacteria on glucose-peptone agar—but develop normally when plated without food on deionised agar.73,74
The single most striking piece of evidence in favour of intercellular interactions is that the ratio of differentiated cell types is approximately invariant with respect to total cell number over two to three orders of magnitude—what has been called ‘the supreme problem of differentiation’ in the cellular slime moulds.54a More to the point, the relative proportions of stalk to spore cells can re-adjust if the developing mass is fragmented, even if most cells in the fragment belong to a single (presumptive) cell type103 (again pointing to relative differences in phenotype rather than absolute phenotype as the essential element that leads to functional differences). The actual proportions of the two differentiated cell types range from about 20:
80 in D. discoideum to 50
:
50 in D. giganteum (for wild type strains studied under standard laboratory conditions).67,104,105
It turns out that in order to account for the magnitude of the fluctuations in cell type proportions (mentioned earlier), one has to invoke, over and above a purely stochastic basis for cell type determination, reciprocal negative feedbacks between the presumptive cell types and an ability on the part of a cell to sense the number of cells in its social group.80
Group integrity within the aggregate is maintained by intercellular adhesion and cell-to-cell signalling. Though all cells take part in these, there are significant differences between the two presumptive cell types in traits related to adhesion and cAMP signalling.106 The bulk of the motive force for the movement of the slug is provided by cells in its front.107 Besides constituting a minority (∼20%) of the total number of cells, these anterior cells die as they become part of the stalk. In an interesting partial overlap with Acytostelium, where the stalk is wholly extracellular, Dictyostelium cells first secrete an extracellular stalk tube, then form the stalk proper by moving into the tube, dying, and synthesising a cellulose wall.53 Eventually the slug stops moving and begins to erect itself while terminal cell differentiation into stalk and spore is taking place. Spore differentiation requires that presumptive stalk cells signal by means of a small peptide SDF-2.108,109 The cells that will eventually sporulate climb up the stalk, and their ascent is helped by two ‘cups’ of cells that cradle the presumptive spore mass from above and below. Of these, the lower cup appears to provide mechanical support while the upper cup actively lifts up the presumptive spore mass.110–111 Neither lower cup cells nor upper cup cells sporulate; they are believed to die while remaining amoeboid in morphology.112
Buss obtained two D. mucoroides strains in close proximity in the soil.60 When studied in isolation, both displayed stable but distinct phenotypes: one went through normal development whereas the other did not. After starved amoebae of the second strain aggregated, all of them differentiated into spores that remained on the surface; the aggregate did not form a stalk. The indications are that the strains were genetically distinct, though they may have been related (there is no evidence bearing on the issue). When mixed, as must have been happening in nature, the two strains developed in concert and formed chimaeric fruiting bodies. However, the two components differentiated in a way that depended on the composition of the mix. When the ratio of ‘stalkless’ to normal amoebae was very low, ‘stalkless’ amoebae were over-represented in the spore population; and when the ratio was very high, the ‘stalkless’ strain formed fewer spores than expected. In other words, there was a frequency dependence of just the sort required for a stable equilibrium to be attained—as turned out to be the case. Thus, everything else being equal, the two would be expected to co-exist stably in nature. In this case, the nature of the interaction is such that it serves little purpose to use words such as parasite, cheater or altruist as descriptors of the phenotype of either strain. Depending on the circumstances, any of these labels can be attached to any of them; it is the dynamics of their interaction that is relevant.
Kawakami and Hagiwara found that P. pallidum strains that belonged to complementary mating types also differed in aspects, including fruiting body morphology, in their asexual life cycles,115 indicating a more usual type of ‘synergism’—mutually beneficial interactions between a pair of individuals belonging to different phenotypes. Moreover, it is an unusual example of genotypes switching roles, by giving rise to sexual dimorphism (in one context) and cooperating within a social group (in another context). This is reminiscent of a school of fish in which an individual of one sex changes into another sex in response to a change in the social structure of the population—for example, when the dominant position falls vacant, except that role-switching in fish is a form of temporal polyethism (for an evolutionary perspective on sequentially hermaphroditic fish, see ref. 116). A curious example of what could be cross-species synergism between a CSM and a fungus was found by Ellison and Buss (though only a benefit to the CSM was established).117 They isolated normal looking fruiting bodies of D. mucorides along with the fungus Mucor hiemalis from soil samples. After purifying the two separately, they noted that when allowed to develop by themselves, the amoebae of D. mucoroides aggregated and differentiated straightaway into a ball of spores; intermediate developmental stages were absent. However, when their environment included fungal hyphae, or if they were provided access to a diffusible substance released by the fungus, the amoebae went through normal development.
Similar experiments were carried out by Weber and Raper,74 who found that two agg− mutants of D. discoideum aggregated and formed normal fruiting bodies when they were put into contact with wild-type D. discoideum amoebae or even amoebae of other species such as D. purpureum and D. mucoroides. A plausible explanation of the outcome comes from the observations of Darmon et al. that the developmental defect in many agg− mutants of D. discoideum could be cured by periodic stimulation of starved cells with extracellular cAMP.88 Ennis et al. isolated a D. discoideum mutant that exhibited aberrant developmental morphology and poor differentiation.122 When mixed with its parental wild-type strain, the mutant participated in normal development and was more efficient than the wild-type at forming spores: its proportions kept increasing with each developmental cycle. Huang et al. showed that a very small proportion of wild-type cells (probably a single cell) was sufficient to initiate development in an otherwise agg− mutant.91 Clark found a low incidence of synergism when pairs of developmentally defective mutants of Polsphondylium violaceum were mixed.123 On the other hand, Rafaeli found that the wild-type and mutant or two different mutants (for example, Stumpy and Fruity) formed chimaeric, normal fruiting bodies.124
Sussman120 and Kahn125 made an extraordinary observation pertaining to synergism in their experiments with D. discoideum and D. purpureum respectively. They reported that a single round of joint development between an agg− mutant and the wild-type (in the course of which mutant cells participated in normal development and differentiated into stalk and spore cells) was sufficient to transform the mutant's phenotype. Thereafter, mutant cells were competent to aggregate and differentiate by themselves. A parallel finding was made by Kaushik.126 She mixed spores of three strains of D. giganteum (46a3gig, 46d2gig and 46c6gig) in pairs as well as in three-way mixtures and grew them in the presence of bacteria for approximately 24 generations. After that, spores from the resulting fruiting bodies were spread with bacteria on nutrient agar plates at a very low density. When they germinated they cleared the bacterial lawn around them forming plaques. Interestingly, many of the plaques when transferred to other plates and allowed to grow and develop further, could not do so. Some of the plaques did not proceed beyond loose aggregations and a few of them did not aggregate at all.
There are also cases from mixed genotype cultures where cells of one genotype repress the development of the other. 50d8, a wild-type strain of D. giganteum, aggregates and forms normal fruiting bodies when by itself, but does so only rarely when mixed with amoebae of the (also wild-type) strains 46a3, 46d2 or 46c6. The inhibitory effect appears to depend on cell-cell contact, because 50d8 develops normally when separated from any of the others by a filter paper barrier.104
Mujumdar et al. (unpublished work) found that when a minority of trishanku mutant cells are mixed with wild-type D. discoideum, aggregation streams break up and fruiting bodies are smaller than normal—phenotypes characteristic of the mutant.131
The antagonism between strains can be mediated via bacteria, which are their normal food. Following growth and starvation, amoebae of the D. discoideum mutant Agg−208 aggregated on a ‘minimal agar’ medium that had been repeatedly washed with distilled water, but did not do so even after the food was exhausted if they were allowed to remain on growth plates; another mutant, Agg−206, did not aggregate under either condition. Co-development of these two mutants on minimal agar led to the partial or complete loss of Agg−208's ability to aggregate.73 Weber and Raper found that two developmentally aberrant mutants of D. dicoideum, agg−-1 and agg−2, aggregated on non-nutrient agar but when grown on plates containing Escherichia coli, did not do so even after food depletion.74
Equally, because they often exist in multi-clonal groups, the CSMs are a useful guide to understanding multicellular development from an evolutionary point of view. On the face of it this appears unlikely—it tends to be taken for granted that all features of development in a clonal embryo can be explained on the basis that what is ‘good for the whole’ is ipso facto ‘good’ for any cell. But there are many reasons for saying that the study of development in a polyclonal group is meaningful for understanding cell behaviour in clonal groups. To begin with, if our interest is in the evolution of group behaviour, what matters is that the group is made up of individuals with different phenotypes and therefore intrinsically different capacities to reproduce (as members of the group); and different phenotypes are just as likely in genetically homogeneous groups as within heterogeneous groups. Second, it has been argued that the reason why only some cells differentiate into germ cells is because by virtue of their phenotypes they out-compete the others and, in a sense, compel them to contribute to somatic tissue,60,142 a line of argument that has also been used to explain the evolution of differentiation in the CSMs.66 Third, the inevitability of somatic mutations implies that so-called clonal development actually involves groups whose members may not be genetically identical.143 Thus CSM development, and by extension that of intra- and inter-specific chimaeric embryos,144,145 may have much to tell us about the evolution of development in general. The life cycle of Dictyostelid amoebae has long been viewed as an example of multicellular development that throws up interesting questions when viewed from an evolutionary perspective. It is time to turn tables and, as integrative biologists, ask what new insights into normal and abnormal development we can gain by thinking about the evolution of cooperative behaviour in the cellular slime moulds. The same point applies with regard to social behaviour in larger animals. The fact that a starved amoeba can differentiate into a spore or stalk cell depending on the phenotypes of other amoebae implies plasticity of a high order. This is mirrored in the functional plasticity displayed by primitively eusocial or facultatively social insects. Workers can take over a queen role when the opportunity presents itself;146 distinct behavioural biases that impinge on social roles can be found in largely solitary species147 and the biases can be overridden by social competition.148
On the basis of studying the evidence for socially selected traits in CSM groups, two broad generalisations may be made. The first is that whenever social selection operates on a phenotype, it is impossible to draw a distinction between ‘cell-autonomous’ and ‘cell-non-autonomous’ effects of the underlying genes. The second is that it is inappropriate to label genotypes by words such as ‘selfish’, ‘altruist’, ‘cheater’ and so on (‘noble’ has joined the list recently). That is because at best such words can convey a verbal description of traits expressed in very specific, and therefore restricted, social settings. In general, they convey nothing about how cells of the same genotype might behave in groups containing some other set of genotypes. Both comments are in the same spirit as that pertaining to the phenotype of a single individual. Namely, it is inappropriate to associate a phenotype with a gene (or allele). Rather, the phenotype results from a complex interplay between allelic activity and the rest of the genome, that too in a specified environment. When every individual is part of every other individual's environment, the phenotype of any one depends on the phenotypes of the rest. In a literal sense, the phenotype of the individual is a social construct.
Moore et al.1 and Frank2 have discussed the principles of social selection with the help of a general method for partitioning phenotypic variance that, as mentioned earlier, was pioneered by Price.21 The method awaits application to genetically heterogeneous groups, especially when their behaviour is pathological. Evidence is accumulating that many cancers can be described as the consequences of social networks that malfunction.149 Among the attendant factors are phenotypic heterogeneities between the members of a cellular group and, just as in ordinary development, reciprocal interactions between cells and their cellular and extracellular environments (i.e., cellular non-autonomy).150–152 But the outcome is to derail the normally stable structure of the group. An analogy has been made recently between groups of cancer cells and species.153 It would be worthwhile to examine whether pathological development, including of the sort that leads to cancer, can be analysed usefully within the Price framework as an example of social selection that has gone awry.
Footnote |
† Published as part of an Integrative Biology themed issue in honour of Mina J. Bissell: Guest Editor Mary Helen Barcellos-Hoff. |
This journal is © The Royal Society of Chemistry 2011 |